Within the psychological tradition, analysis of students' utterances
has focused on the 'transactional' function of language in the expression
of 'factual' propositional content. The clinical interview is an effective
means of eliciting data with this (though not only this) objective (Rowland,
1999a, b). The purpose of this paper is to emphasise that language also
fulfils an essential 'interactional' function in expressing social relations
and propositional attitude, and to argue for the significance of such
dimensions in the analysis of discourses of a mathematical nature. The
paper explicates the nature of 'pragmatic'(1) meaning,
reviews some approaches to discourse rooted in or related to speech act
theory (Austin, 1962; Searle, 1969), and concludes with analysis of a
fragment of text for illustrative purposes.
MEANING
There exist a number of accounts of 'meaning' within natural language.
Accounts differ partly because of different perspectives deriving from
linguistics, philosophy, psychology, sociology, literary criticism, theology,
and so on. In discussing meaning in this paper, I have in mind a view
of communication that focuses on human intention, and my starting point
is what the philosopher Paul Grice (1957) called 'speaker meaning'. Grice
distinguishes between two kinds of meaning: natural and non-natural. The
first of these might be called the semantic or truth-conditional meaning
of sentences such as:
if x>2 then x2>4
This is meaning of a conventional, literal kind. Of course, such a notion
is not unproblematic, pre-supposing as it does that words and symbols
refer to things in an unambiguous way, and that the syntax of the sentence
then takes care of the meaning.
Non-natural meaning is associated with (human) communication which is
intended to be received in a particular way by a recipient. This is the
'pragmatic' meaning, which may be conventional, but certainly need not
be in the case, for example, of ironic, metaphorical and indirect communications.
A critical feature of non-natural meaning is the particular way that it
is intended to be recognised and interpreted by a recipient. The
distinction between the truth-conditional, semantic meaning and the pragmatic
meaning of an utterance is demonstrated by B's turn in the following interchange.
A: Do you think you'll get back home in time to cut the grass?
B: Well, I'll try, but there are road works on the A14 this week.
The semantic content of the reply is to the effect that B will endeavour
to get home on time, and that there are works on a particular road. In
practice, we read much more into it. Even in the absence of 'well', we
might infer inter alia that:
- B will travel by road;
- the road works on the A14 might cause B to be delayed;
- B is not confident that s/he will be home in time to cut the grass.
The inclusion of 'well' adds an additional dimension to the reply: that
is, B's anticipation that his or her reply is not the one that A would
like to hear (Wierzbicka, 1976; Brockway, 1981).
In an account of the 'transactional' and 'interactional' functions(2)
of language, Brown and Yule touch on a distinction which seems to parallel
that between semantic and pragmatic meaning.
That function which language serves in the expression of content we
describe as transactional, and that function involved in expressing
social relations we will describe as interactional.
Whereas linguists, philosophers of language and psycholinguists have,
in general, paid attention to the use of language for the transmission
of 'factual propositional information', sociologists and sociolinguists
have been particularly concerned with the use of language to negotiate
role-relationships, peer-solidarity, the exchange of turns in a conversation,
the saving of face of both speaker and hearer. (Brown and Yule 1983,
pp. 1-4) (3)
The importance of the transactional function of language in the teaching
and learning of mathematics is self-evident. Michael Halliday, a linguist,
leaves us in no doubt as to the educational significance of the interactional
function.
If we consider the language of a child, there is good evidence to suggest
that control over language in its interpersonal function is as crucial
to educational success as its control over the expression of content,
for it is through this function that the child learns to participate,
as an individual, and to express and develop his own personality and
his own uniqueness. (Halliday, 1976, pp. 197?8)
Pragmatic meaning is the means frequently (though not necessarily consciously)
used by speakers to convey affective messages to do with social relations,
attitudes and beliefs, or to associate or distance themselves from the
propositions they articulate. That is to say, pragmatic meaning is an
important tool in fulfilling the interactional function of language.
Shiffrin (1994) and Jaworski and Coupland (1999) give excellent surveys
of a wide range of approaches to discourse which are particularly sensitive
to pragmatic meaning and interactional function. The following sections
of this paper give a necessarily brief overview of three contributions
to pragmatic analysis. Each points to possible means whereby non-natural
meaning might be conveyed by a speaker, and each will play a part in the
scrutiny of a teaching episode towards the end of this paper.
SPEECH ACTS
In the late 1950s, the Oxford philosopher John Austin gave some lectures
on how speakers "do things with words", and so invented a theory
of 'speech acts' (Austin, 1962) which now occupies a central place in
pragmatics. The essential property of speech acts is that they bring about
(or have the potential to bring about) a change in some state of affairs.
Paradigm examples include the naming of a ship, the joining of two persons
in marriage, and the sentencing of a criminal. The name, the marriage
and the sentence are what they are because an authorised person has declared
them to be so. Austin distinguished between the locution of a speech
act (the words uttered), its illocution (the intention of the speaker
in making the utterance) and its perlocution (its effects, intended
or otherwise).
Whereas declarative utterances typically have truth conditions, speech
acts must satisfy certain 'felicity conditions' in order to 'count' as
an action. For example, the felicity conditions for a question
include the expectation that the enquirer doesn't know the answer, that
s/he would like to know it, and has reason to believe the hearer is able
to supply it. Questions in classroom situations are curiously exempted
from these rules (Labov and Fanshel, 1977).
One aspect of speech act theory with significant pragmatic implications
concerns indirectness. Three broad illocutionary categories are
normally identified - statement, question and command/request - having
typical realisations in declarative, interrogative and imperative verb
forms. These agreements between intended function and realised form break
down in 'indirect speech acts', in which the outward (locutionary) form
of an utterance does not correspond with the intended illocutionary force
of the speech act which it performs (Levinson, 1983, pp. 263ff). Common
forms of this are to declare a preference or to use an interrogative form
in order to convey an order or request. For example:
Teacher: I'd like to take in your exercise books.
Diner: Can you bring me the wine list?
These are both instances of how speakers frequently accomplish an indirect
speech act by stating or questioning one of the felicity conditions (Gordon
and Lakoff, 1971). The teacher explicitly states his wish to receive
the books i.e. that s/he meets the felicity condition to do with speaker
sincerity; the diner questions the ability of the waiter to provide
the list i.e. s/he questions one of the preparatory pre-conditions.
POLITENESS
So why should speakers in general, and teachers in particular, be indirect
in this way?
One insight into such indirectness in classroom mathematics talk is provided
by a sociolinguistic theory of 'politeness' developed in the late 1970s.
This theory claims that speakers avoid threats to the 'face' of those
they address by various forms of indirectness, vagueness, and so on, and
thereby 'implicate' (hint at) their meanings rather than assert them directly.
Politeness theory (Brown and Levinson, 1987) is based on the notion that
participants are rational beings, but with two kinds of 'face wants' connected
with their public self-image:
- positive face - a desire to be appreciated and valued by others; desire
for approval;
- negative face - concern for certain personal rights and freedoms,
such as autonomy to choose actions, claims on territory, and so on;
desire to be unimpeded.
Now some acts ('face threatening acts', or FTAs) intrinsically threaten
face. Orders and requests, for example, threaten negative face, whereas
criticism and disagreement threaten positive face. The perpetrator therefore
must either avoid such acts altogether (which may be impossible for a
host of reasons, including concern for her/his own face) or find ways
of performing them whilst mitigating their FTA effect.
Brown and Levinson identify and catalogue a number of related linguistic
strategies, including quasi-interrogative commands (such as that of the
Diner, above) which redress the threat to the addressee's negative face,
their autonomy, respecting their right to refuse. These include conventionally
polite, indirect speech acts such as "Can you pass the salt, please?".
HEDGES
The linguist George Lakoff coined the term 'a hedge' for a word or phrase
that makes a proposition "fuzzy" or vague in some way (Lakoff,
1972). A hedge can be categorised either as a 'shield' or as an 'approximator'.
Maybe, probably and possibly are examples of so-called 'plausibility
shields', which stand outside a substantive proposition (e.g. '[Maybe]
we should call a taxi') and point to something less than complete commitment
to it. One of the functions of shield-hedges is to protect the speaker
from accusation of being committed to a false proposition (Channell, 1994).
Incidentally, teachers more often use 'attribution shields' such as "so-and-so
says that
", distancing themselves from a proposition by attributing
it to someone else. This is a pedagogical strategy which avoids 'closing'
on a problem, in order to sustain discussion and invite a variety of proposals.
For example:
Teacher: John says you can't divide 739 by 9. What do other people think?
Approximators such as about, around and approximately, as
well as sort of, kind of and basically, can, like
shields. also have the effect of withholding commitment to a proposition.
They achieve this by inserting vagueness into the substantive proposition
itself (e.g. 'The taxi will be here in [about] ten minutes').
Here, a 14-year-old boy makes a prediction, but the vagueness of his answer
suggests that it was far from secure:
Allan: The maximum will probably be, er, the least'll probably be 'bout
fifteen.
Allan hedges his prediction in two ways : the shield 'probably' is reinforced
with the approximator '(a)bout'. The very act of complying with the teacher's
request for a prediction is a threat to Allan's positive face, since he
could be thought foolish if his prediction were subsequently found to
be in error. The shield makes his lack of commitment explicit; use of
the approximator 'about' is a more subtle protective strategy, for it
renders Allan's answer "almost unfalsifiable" (Sadock, 1977,
p. 437).
There follows a fragment from one mathematics lesson. The discussion of
the interaction here focuses on the pragmatic meanings of some of the
utterances within the text, with concern for the beliefs and attitudes
of the three participants towards the subject-matter and each other. The
choice of this fragment is to some extent determined by the 'conjecturing
atmosphere' (Mason, 1988, p. 9) that permeates the episode. It is this
factor, I believe, that makes the 'conversation' below a special kind
of discourse. As I have argued in Rowland (1999b), such an atmosphere
involves the student (and possibly the teacher) in taking risks, in articulating
generalisations on the basis of partial evidence. Evidence of the management
of such risks, by teacher and student, is to be found in pragmatic discourse
analysis. The discussion which follows also involves reference to aspects
of justification and proof which have not been previewed in this introduction,
but will be familiar to researchers in mathematics education.
DISCOURSE ANALYSIS: HAZEL
Hazel, an elementary school teacher, describes 10-year-old Faye and Donna
as able mathematicians who often work together. Her discussion with them
is essentially an exploration of the following problem.
Take three equally spaced numbers, such as 10, 13, 16. Find the product
of the outer pair [10x16=160] and the square of the middle term [13x13=169].
The difference is 9. What will happen if you take other similar number-triples?
What if you take a common difference other than 3?
Hazel's conversation with the two girls falls into four episodes, the
first of which is the main focus for this analysis:
- Episode 1: Investigation of the case when the common difference is
1 [turns 1-61]
- Episode 2: Investigation of the case when the common difference is
2 [62-105]
- Episode 3: Investigation of the case when the common difference is
3 [106-120]
- Episode 4: Search for a higher-level generalisation which includes
the three generalisations arrived at inductively in the previous episodes
as special cases [121-160].
In every case Hazel's instructions and requests to the two girls are presented
as indirect speech acts, for example (there are many):
17 Hazel: Shall we try it out and see what happens? Do you want to each
choose your own set of consecutive numbers?
66 Hazel: Right would you like to try out with ten, twelve and fourteen
one of you and the other one can try another jump.
130 Hazel: Can you tell me what the difference in the answers of the
two sums that, the two multiplications you're doing would be when you
have a difference of four between each number?
17 and 66 are on-record FTAs, 'orders' presented as questions out of respect
for the children's negative face, as Hazel imposes on their personal autonomy
of action. These are conventionally indirect. She believes that the investigation
will be a worthwhile, educative experience for them with a potentially
stimulating outcome. Nonetheless she recognises the risk-taking which
is inherent in her quasi-empirical approach, and that she requires their
cooperation as active participants in the project as they generate confirming
instances of generalisations-to-come. In [17] she says "Shall we
try it out?", the plural form including and identifying herself as
a partner in the enterprise. In [130] she probes for a prediction, and
realises the threat to the girls' positive face - what if they fail to
make a correct prediction, will their reputation as "good mathematicians"
be dented? [130] respects their positive face, and the indirect modal
form redresses the on-record FTA. These features of Hazel's language are
manifestations of her 'sensitivity to students' (Jaworski, 1994). Fallibilistic
teaching, inviting conjectures and the associated intellectual risks is
unimaginable if the teacher is not aware of the FTAs that are likely to
be woven into her/his questions and 'invitations' to active participation.
Redressive action dulls the sharp edge of the interactive demands that
this style places on the learner. For Hazel, notwithstanding her authority
in her own classroom, the indirect speech act has become a pedagogic habit.
Early in the conversation, Faye [9] observes a difference of 1 between
10x12 and 112. Somewhat precipitately, perhaps, Hazel asks:
10 Hazel: One number difference ... do you think that will always happen
when we do this ... ?
Faye readily agrees, but Hazel, perhaps realising that she has not probed
but has 'led the witness' seems to want to give them more of an option
to disagree.
12 Hazel: What makes you think that? Just 'cos I asked it ... or ...?
Donna gives hedged agreement [14]: Hazel invites her [15] to account
for her provisional belief.
14 Donna: I think so.
15 Hazel: Why?
Arguably this is a tough question - to account for a belief that one is
not really committed to anyway. Donna's justification [16] is phenomenological
rather than structural.
16 Donna: Well if um ... if it's after each other like ten, eleven,
twelve ... um ... it will be one more because it's one more going up.
It is the basis of a subsequent higher-level generalisation at the beginning
of Episode 2.
62 Hazel: Okay. Right, what would happen if you had numbers that jumped
up in two instead of one, so you had ten, twelve and fourteen?
63 Faye: I think the answer is a two number difference. So two.
64 Donna: Yeah, yeah. So do I.
The substantive proposition in [63] - that there is a two number difference
- is, in fact, false. By prefacing it with a Shield, Faye marks her utterance
as a conjecture, withholding commitment to it.
Returning to Episode 1: Hazel encourages the children to try out two more
examples with three consecutive integers. They obtain a difference of
1 in each case and Faye [27] affirms her belief (unhedged) that, as Hazel
puts it [26], "that will always happen".
26 Hazel: Do you think that will always happen then?
27 Faye: Yes.
28 Hazel: How can you say for certain 'cos you've only tried out three
examples?
Donna offers a brief diversion:
35 Donna: I don't think it will happen if you do like eleven, fourteen,
twenty-two.
36 Hazel: But you're talking about the one that ... if you always have
a set of three consecutive numbers will it work?
Her "like eleven, fourteen, twenty-two" is a delightful example
of a vague generality; what like-ness does she intend to point to with
this single example? It is difficult to judge how Hazel interprets it,
except that she takes it to exclude "three consecutive numbers"
- and perhaps this is precisely what Donna intended to convey through
her example. Evidently 'consecutive' is a useful but neglected item in
the mathematical lexicon.
Faye brings the discussion back on course with a request for a what philosophers
of science might call a 'crucial experiment' (Balacheff, 1988) - testing
the conjecture with an example well outside the range so far considered,
to explore the extent of its validity.
38 Faye: I'd like to try it out in the hundreds.
Donna's choice for the experiment seems to be guided by Hazel:
39 Hazel: [to Donna] You want one difference between each of those.
If you're going to start with a hundred you could have a hundred and
one, a hundred and one and a hundred and two. Would you like a calculator
...?
Faye makes an independent choice [60] of 110, 111, 112:
51 Faye: I still get one number different.
52 Hazel: So that ... so do you ... will it always work d'you think?
53 Faye: Yeah ... I think.
54 Hazel: How can you be sure?
55 Donna: Umm
56 Faye: [laughing] Well ...
57 Hazel: Are you sure?
58 Faye: Well not really, but ...
59 Donna: Quite yeah.
60 Faye: I think so. Yeah quite sure. Because it has worked because
we've done ten, eleven ... Well I've done ten, eleven, twelve, nine,
ten, eleven which are quite similar and then I've jumped to, um, um
... a hundred and ten, a hundred and eleven, and a hundred and twelve.
It's quite a big difference. So yeah?
61 Donna: Yeah so do I.
By this stage Hazel seems reluctant [52] to influence their commitment
to the generalisation (the 'it' that 'always works'). Faye's intellectual
honesty is very evident here. Her crucial experiment [60] provides another
(presumably weighty) confirming instance of the generalisation [51] yet
her assent to it is still hedged, partial [53]. One senses that Hazel
has created, or nurtured, a 'Zone of Conjectural Neutrality' (Rowland,
1999b) in which Faye understands that it is the conjecture ('it always
works') which is on trial, not herself. She is free to believe or to doubt.
Nevertheless, her 'well's [56, 58] indicate that she senses, perhaps,
that it would be easier if she agreed - that agreement would better respect
Hazel's positive face wants - for Hazel would gain satisfaction from Faye's
coming-to-know.
CONCLUSION
Classroom talk is a rich resource for the analysis of students' cognitive
structuring of mathematics, in which student errors are a particularly
rich basis for conjectures about fundamental mathematical misconceptions.
Such analyses provide essential diagnostic insights into individual knowledge
construction. Reports of such analyses are typically set within a framework
of knowledge about mathematical cognition. This may be of a general kind,
to do with concept formation, abstraction and so on, or related to knowledge
about the construction of knowledge in particular topic areas such as
fractions or functions.
Concern for more interactional features of the classroom, such as students'
propositional attitudes and teachers' sensitivity to their students' self-esteem,
necessitates rather a different set of lenses and analytical tools from
which to view texts. Linguistic tools which focus on pragmatic meaning
have significant potential for text analysis in mathematics education,
especially in research into social and affective factors in the teaching
and learning of mathematics. Further evidence of this potential is given
in Rowland (1999b). A recent paper by Bills (2000) explores the prevalence,
purpose and effect of a range of politeness strategies in mathematical
dialogue involving a teacher and two 17-year-old students.
Any analysis of classroom interaction involves the selection and application
of analytic perspectives, and pragmatic tools are as yet novel in the
field of mathematics education. It will be interesting to see what further
insights they yield for researchers as they come into more general use,
what the pedagogical application of such insights might be, and whether
teachers perceive them as valuable.
REFERENCES
Austin, J. L. (1962) How to Do Things with Words, Oxford, Oxford
University Press.
Balacheff, N. (1988) 'Aspects of proof in pupils' practice of school mathematics',
in Pimm, D. (ed.) Mathematics, Teachers and Children. London, Hodder
and Stoughton, pp. 216-235.
Bills, L. (2000) 'Politeness in teacher-student dialogue in mathematics:
a socio-linguistic analysis'. For the Learning of Mathematics 20,
pp. 40-47.
Brockway, D. (1981) 'Semantic constraints on relevance', in Parrett, H.,
Sbisa, M. and Verschueren, J. (eds), Possibilities and Limitations
of Pragmatics: Proceedings of the Conference on Pragmatics at Urbino,
July 8-14, 1979, Amsterdam, Benjamins, pp. 57-78.
Brown, P, and Levinson, S. C. (1987) Politeness: some universals in
language usage, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Brown, G. and Yule, G. (1983) Discourse Analysis, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press.
Channell, J. M. (1994) Vague Language. Oxford: Oxford University
Press..
Gordon, D. and Lakoff, G. (1971) 'Conventional postulates', Papers
from the Seventh Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistics Society,
Chicago, Chicago Linguistic Society, pp. 63-84.
Grice, H. P. (1957) 'Meaning'. Philosophical Review, 67, pp. 377-388.
Halliday, M. A. K. (1976) 'Modality and modulation in English' in Kress,
G. R. (ed.) Halliday: system and function in language. London,
Oxford University Press, pp. 189-213.
Jacobson, R. (1960) 'Closing statement: linguistics and poetics'. In Seebook,
T. A. (ed.) Style in Language. Cambridge, NA: MIT press, pp. 350-77.
Jaworski, A. and Coupland, N. (1999) The Discourse Reader. London:
Routledge.
Jaworski, B. (1994) Investigating Mathematics Teaching. London:
Falmer Press.
Labov. W. and Fanshel, D. (1977) Therapeutic Discourse: psychotherapy
as conversation, New York, Academic Press.
Lakoff, G. (1972) 'Hedges: a study in meaning criteria and the logic of
fuzzy concepts', Papers from the Eighth Regional Meeting of the Chicago
Linguistics Society, Chicago, Chicago Linguistic Society, pp. 183-228.
Levinson, S. C. (1983) Pragmatics, Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press.
Mason, J. (1988) Learning and Doing Mathematics. London, Macmillan.
Rowland, T. (1999a) 'The clinical interview: conduct and interpretation'.
In Zaslavsky, O. (ed.) Proceedings of the 23rd Conference of the International
Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education. Vol. 4, pp. 129-136.
Haifa, Israel. Israel Institute of Technology.
Rowland, T. (1999b) The Pragmatics of Mathematics Education: vagueness
and mathematical discourse. London: Falmer.
Sadock, J. M. (1977) 'Truth and approximations', Berkeley Linguistic
Society Papers, 3, pp. 430-439.
Schiffrin, D. (1994) Approaches to Discourse, Oxford, Basil Blackwell.
Searle, J. (1969) Speech Acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Stubbs, M. (1986) ''A matter of prolonged fieldwork': notes towards a
modal grammar of English', Applied Linguistics, 7(1), pp. 1-25.
Wierzbicka, A. (1976) 'Particles and Linguistic Relativity', International
Review of Slavic Linguistics 1(2-3), pp. 327-367.
NOTES
- It should soon become clear that "pragmatic"
is used here, and throughout in this paper, in a technical sense, so
that it means something more specific than just "expedient"
or "dogma-free".
- This binary subdivision of the functions of language
is adequate for our present purposes. A finer taxonomy of speech functions
due to Roman Jakobson (1960) identifies six functions: referential,
emotive, conative, phatic, metalingual and poetic.
- Grice and Austin demonstrate that philosophers
of language are by no means exclusively preoccupied with transaction.
|